Propositional logic classifies propositions into main categories: true and false. Alethic modal logic makes distinctions between different modes in which a proposition may be true or false. The formal framework of modal logic expands the language of propositional logic with a sentential operator,
Other interpretations of the formalism take the sentential operators in question to provide a different qualification to the proposition expressed by the sentence in question.
Example 1.1 (Modal Ontological Argument) Given the nature of numbers, necessarily, if they exist at all, then they are necessary beings. It is at least possible that numbers exist. So, it is possible that numbers are necessary beings. It follows that there are numbers.
In premise-conclusion form, the argument becomes:
The argument is propositionally invalid, but it nevertheless retains a measure of plausibility. If we let
Example 1.2 (Aristotle's Sea Battle) If there is a sea battle tomorrow, Aristotle reasons, then it was already the case in the past that there would be a sea battle tomorrow. But that could have not been otherwise, since the past is closed. However, if it is necessary that it was the case that there would be a sea battle tomorrow, then it should still be necessary that there will be a sea battle tomorrow. So, if there is a sea battle tomorrow, then it is already necessary that there will be one.
Aristotle appears to take as a point of departure the thought that whatever we think of the future, the past is closed. To the extent to which we cannot change the past, whatever was the case must have been the case. Aristotle’s argument is meant to target the alleged contrast between past and future: it is incoherent to suppose that the future is open if the past is already closed.
The argument relies now on the interaction between different modalities, two temporal ones such as
The question of validity is more complicated than in the earlier example as this argument takes place in a multi-modal language with temporal and alethic modal operators.
Let us return to the question of how to interpret the formalism of propositional modal logic. There is, in particular, an important contrast to be drawn between propositional logic and propositional modal logic.
We are able to use truth tables to interpret the language of propositional logic because propositional connectives are truth-functional, e.g., the truth value of a conjunction is a function of the truth values of its conjuncts. The strategy does not seem to be available in the case of modal logic, since the modal operator
When
One may attempt to overcome this limitation with the help of a more fine-grained distinction between necessary and contingent truths, on the one hand, and necessary and contingent falsehoods, on the other. We may even reserve the letters
When
We must look elsewhere for an interpretation of the formalism of propositional modal logic. One key observation at this point is that propositions differ not just with respect to whether they are true or false, they may differ with respect to the circumstances under which they are true or false. The propositions expressed by the statements ‘Los Angeles has over three million inhabitants’ and ‘Kilimanjaro rises to 5,895 meters’ are both true but there are possible circumstances under which one is true and the other is false.
We may think of possible worlds as complete specifications of a way the world might be, and we may ask whether a sentence is true at a possible world. That is, we may ask whether the possible world in question specifies circumstances under which the sentence is in fact true.
Once we take on board the thought that a sentence may be true when evaluated with respect to one possible world but not when evaluated with respect to another, we may ask what is for a possible world to be possible relative to another. The proposition that I’m a philosopher is true given how the world is, but there are possible circumstances under which I’m an engineer. We codify that as the thought that a world at which I’m an engineer is possible with respect to the world of evaluation. We will call a possible world is accessible from another world if the former is possible with respect to the latter.
We now have the basic ingredients for a possible world semantics for propositional modal logic. More formally, a model for the framework will consist of a collection of possible worlds
Example 1.3 (A Possible Worlds Model) Here is a depiction of a possible worlds model, which consists of a set
A negation
A material conditional
A formula
A formula
Consider the premises and conclusion of the modal formalization of the argument with which we started:
Therefore,
It follows that
It will turn out that the validity of the argument for the existence of numbers turns on the structure of the accessibility relation. That is, the argument will be valid when we restrict attention to models in which the accessibility relation is either symmetric or models in which the accessibility relation is reflexive and euclidean.1 Please do not worry if any of those terms are new to you. Much of what we will do before we formally introduce the language of propositional modal logic is to cover some preliminaries, which will include some discussion of the structure of binary relations.