We expand the language of quantificational logic
The vocabulary of the language
We will continue to use
We now explain how to combine the symbols of the vocabulary into well-formed formulas of the language of quantified modal logic.
Definition 16.1 (Atomic Formula) We define what is for a string of symbols to be an atomic formula of
If
Nothing else is an atomic formula.
Definition 16.2 (Well-Formed Formula) We now define what is for a string to be a well-formed formula of
The set
We now define familiar connectives in terms of
Definition 16.3
The inductive definition of well-formed formula vindicates a principle of induction for well-formed formulas, which will help us prove different generalizations over them.
Proposition 16.1 (Induction on the Complexity of Well-Formed Formulas) Given a condition
then every formula of
The simplest quantified modal logic combines the axioms of quantificational logic with identity with the axioms of the minimal normal modal logic K. That will motivate a simple possible worlds model theory for the language, one that has, however, been controversial. In order to be in a position to discuss the framework, we should review the axioms of quantificational logic with identity.
The axioms for quantificational logic with identity include:
Substitution instances of axioms of propositional logic for the expanded language.
Substitution instances of the axiom of universal instantiation:
where
Two rules of inference:
We are in a position prove some derived rules of inference from them:
We adopt all substitution instances of the axioms of quanficational logic with identity for the expanded language, which we supplement with the axioms and rules of inference for the minimal normal modal logic:
We now derive three remarkable consequences of the axioms of quantified modal logic with identity.
One consequence of the axioms is the Converse Barcan Formula (CBF):
The Barcan Formula (BF) is not a theorem of the simplest quantified modal logic, as we have described it, but its instances become derivable in the presence of axiom schema B.
Existence is generally understood in terms of quantification and identity: to exist is to be identical with something. But the simplest quantified modal logic has the resources to prove that everything is necessarily identical to something, which would appear to mean that necessarily, everything — including you and me — necessarily exists.
Here is a simple derivation:
We are in a position to establish the necessity of identity.
Here is a derivation:
One reaction to the derivability of the Barcan Formula and its converse in the simplest quantified modal logic is to regard it as a reason to weaken the axioms for the quantifier. Free quantified modal logic makes do with a restricted form of universal instantiation. Before we look at the details, we should however mention that there are independent reasons to consider such a restriction.
Some philosophers have questioned quantificational logic on the grounds that it delivers objectionable theorems such as existential generalization:
Existential generalization delivers problematic consequences in the presence of terms without denotation. For suppose we expand the language of quantificational logic with constants some of which are meant to translate singular terms without a denotation, e.g., ‘Pegasus’. One problem is that existential generalization delivers:
Existential generalization allows us to move from a universal generalization to an existential one:
One response to these observations is to restrict the axiom of unversal instantiation to avoid the full strength of existential generalization. This in turn may be done in more than one way resulting in different approaches to quantified modal logic.
We will look at two main restrictions of the axiom of universal instantiation. One of them is directly motivated by the derivability of the Converse Barcan formula in the simplest quantified modal logic, whereas the other is motivated by the ambition to accommodate free expansions of quantificational logic in which singular terms are allowed to lack a denotation.
We begin with a proposal due to Saul Kripke who weakens universal instantiation as follows:
Actually, the flaw lies in the application of necessitation to [1]. In a formula like [1], we give the free variables the generality interpretation: when [1] is asserted as a theorem, it abbreviates an assertion of its ordinary universal closure:
Now, if we applied necessitation to [1’], we would get On the other hand, [2] itself is interpreted as asserting: To infer [2’’] from [2’], we would need a law of the form , which is just the converse Barcan formula we are trying to prove […]. We can avoid this sort of difficulty if, following Quine, we formulate quantification theory so that only closed formulae are asserted. Assertion of formulae containing free variables is at best a convenience; assertion of with free can always be replaced by assertion of .
So, Kripke’s suggestion is to block the application of necessitation to open formulas by adopting a formulation of quantificational logic without open formulas as axioms. Hence the proposal to weaken UI to KFUI, which is its universal closure. As it turns out, Kripke’s proposal requires the adoption of a further quantificational axiom:
The other approach to free quantificational logic is designed to accommodate singular terms without a denotation. That is, the approach is supposed to accommodate the introduction of new constants, which fail to denote a member of the domain. The thought in this case is to augment the language of quantificational logic with a primitive existence predicate
Given such a predicate, we are in a position to reformulate free universal instantiation as follows:
One difference between this move and Kripke’s move is that it allows for the use of open formulas as axioms of quantificational logic and provides a different response to the argument for the necessity of existence. All we are able to do now is the following: